A Left-Libertarian Primer
|
|
Nick
Ford | March 20th, 2015 |
|
Many thanks to the more than
helpful edits of Kyler Dineen and Mike Moceri |
|
The “Left” in Left-Libertarian
|
|
The goal of this paper isn’t to
convince anyone of the benefits of anarchism or to convince anyone that they
should be a left-libertarian. Instead, I’d like to help deepen our understanding
of what the position entails and what activities people who subscribe to the
philosophy may support. |
|
I want to start by talking about the
contentious use of the word “left.” |
|
Some people are probably familiar
with someone “on the left” being a Democrat, a state-socialist or a communist.
But the term has a broader meaning. I use it to refer to people like the anarchist
David Graeber or the historian Howard Zinn. Left-libertarians are more likely to
draw influences from folks who are radically subverting or questioning the status
quo. “Democrat,” therefore, is not synonymous with “the left.” |
|
There are a few useful ways that I’ve
found to define the term “left,” one of which is attributed to Gary Chartier,
a professor at La Sierra University. The leftist, according to Chartier in his
article The
“Left” in Left Libertarian, “…is marked by opposition to
subordination, exclusion, and deprivation.” |
|
Chartier explains: |
|
Chartier argues that all of these
things concern vulnerability. |
|
Opposing vulnerability, however, isn’t
enough. A particular method for opposing it is necessary. There is a difference
between means and ends, though. I don’t think (and neither does Chartier) that
exclusion is inherently bad, just that it is generally suspect to a leftist. A “leftist”
usually considers the facts and ensures that said opposition is legitimate before
acting on it. |
|
The notable leftist Cornel West says
on the meaning of being a leftist: |
|
[being] concerned about structural violence, you
are concerned about exploitation at the work place, you are concerned about
institutionalized contempt against gay brothers and lesbian sisters, hatred
against peoples of color, and the subordination of women. It means that you are
willing to fight against, and to try to understand the sources of social misery at
the structural and institutional levels, as well as at the existential and
personal levels. |
|
It’s also notable that West’s
definition relies on two of Chartier’s themes, exclusion and subordination, and
amplifies them with real world examples. |
|
Another approach is attributed to Karl
Hess, a prominent libertarian in the 60s through the 80s. He used a more
historical than philosophical or contemporary/real world model. He talks about the
left and right being divided by their interest in concentrations of power and
wealth. |
|
According to Hess, the historical
left has always been marked by “…politics and economics that opposes the
concentration of power and wealth and, instead, advocates and works toward the
distribution of power into the maximum number of hands.” He defines “the right”
by its impulse to do the opposite. |
|
This doesn’t mean, as Hess points
out, that if you push a conservative enough they’ll want to institute a monarchy
or dictatorship, but rather that, “the ghosts of royal power whisper in the
conservative tradition.” |
|
These three approaches are
conversation starters, and not enders. One might say that “None of the
self-described leftists I know are like that,” and that’s fine. I’m sure
there are people who identify as leftists even though they have none of the
concerns that Chartier, West, and Hess address. However, these three authors give
us a more comprehensive view of “the left” than the colloquial meaning
provides. |
|
I think left-libertarianism fits
comfortably under all three approaches. I don’t contend that these are perfect
definitions or that they perfectly encapsulate what you’d find in your average
left-libertarian. But I do think they help start the conversation. |
|
The “Libertarian” in Left-Libertarian
|
|
If we take from “left” to mean
opposition to subordination, deprivation, and exclusion, where does the “libertarianism”
come in? |
|
Libertarianism has a closer link to
radicalism than modern-day progressivism. It’s a practical philosophy for
building a less subordinating, depriving, and exclusive society. As Marx might
say, “Philosophers have spent their time speaking about the world, but the real
goal is to change it.” Libertarians challenge us to do that. |
|
While there are some outliers (I am
specifically thinking of Bleeding
Heart Libertarians who may identify also as left-libertarians or Chris
Matthew Sciabarra, a kind of left-Objectivist who is also a minarchist), for
the most part left-libertarians see their libertarianism as rooted in certain
traditions and figures more closely aligned with anarchism than minarchism. I’ll
cite three examples: |
|
So the “libertarianism” invoked
here has much more to do with something like market anarchism than minarchism. But
there are exceptions. |
|
One such exception would be so-called
Bleeding Heart Libertarians. Some people think they are the same as
left-libertarians. I’d like to make it clear that while there is some definite
overlap, but they are not the same thing. |
|
Furthering this point, I’ll quote
Roderick Long from his article, Left
Libertarianism: Its Past, Its Present, Its Prospects: |
|
Insofar as BHL represents a fusion of the
free-market commitments of libertarianism with the social-justice concerns of the
left, left-libertarianism may be counted as a subset of BHL; but left-libertarians
tend to be more radical, in both their leftism and their libertarianism, than the
majority of those self-identifying as BHL proponents. … Most BHL proponents
appear to see their libertarian commitments and their left-wing commitments as at
least to some extent moderating each other; left-libertarians, by contrast, tend
to see their libertarian and leftist commitments as mainly reinforcing each other.
… One might say that if the dominant BHL aim is to fuse Hayek with Rawls, the
dominant left-libertarian aim is to fuse Murray Rothbard with David Graeber. |
|
The Theory of Left-Libertarianism in Practice
|
|
With this background in mind, how
does the radical leftism of Chartier, West, and Hess mesh with the radical
libertarianism of folks like Spooner and the left-fusionism of the 60s and early
70s? |
|
I’ll draw on a few notable examples
that mesh leftist concepts with popular libertarian theories or theorists. |
|
First, in Charles Johnson’s essay, Women
and the Invisible Fist, he links the notion of Hayekian spontaneous order with
the radical feminist notion of rape culture: |
|
Brownmiller holds that rape culture involves some
conscious, centrally-coordinated campaigns – such as the use of rape as a weapon
of war in conflicts between male governed nation states. But her understanding of
rape culture crucially depends on the structural effects of widely dispersed
actions, which are carried out by a “swarm of men” acting “in anonymity,”
rather than by governments or organized bodies of men acting on a centrally
directed plan; this ought to suggest a very clear and direct parallel to Hayek’s
characterizations of spontaneous order as polycentric order, more akin to “organism”
than to “organization.” The undirected but systematic actions of the “swarm”
of Myrmidon rapists have profound social effects but, because of their very
anonymity, “police blotter rapists have performed their duty … so well …
that the true meaning of their act has largely gone unnoticed”; just as Hayek
characterizes spontaneous orders in such terms as “the unintended and often
uncomprehended results of the separate and yet interrelated actions of men [sic]
in society.” |
|
(I do not have the space within this
essay to defend radical feminism, but if you’re curious more about where
feminism and libertarianism intersect I heartily recommend Charles Johnson and
Roderick Long’s, Libertarian
Feminism: Can this Marriage be Saved?) |
|
Second, Kevin Carson, in an article
called Economic
Calculation in the Corporate Commonwealth, draws rather explicitly on Mises’
calculation critiques of state-socialism and Hayekian knowledge problem
critiques of state-socialism and applies both to the modern corporation. |
|
He explains: |
|
The basic cause of calculational chaos, as Mises
understood it, was the separation of entrepreneurial from technical knowledge and
the attempt to make production decisions based on technical considerations alone,
without regard to such entrepreneurial considerations as factor pricing. But the
principle also works the other way: production decisions based solely on input and
product prices, without regard to the details of production (the typical MBA
practice of considering only finance and marketing, while treating the production
process as a black box), also result in calculational chaos. |
|
To compare, consider Hayek’s prediction of the
uneven development, irrationality, and misallocation of resources within a planned
economy (“Socialist Calculation II: The State of the Debate”)… |
|
… As an example, [Hayek] cited “the excellence,
from a technological point of view, of some parts of the Russian industrial
equipment, which often strikes the casual observer and which is commonly regarded
as evidence of success.” |
|
To anyone observing the uneven development of the
corporate economy under state capitalism, this should inspire a sense of déjà
vu. Entire categories of goods and production methods have been developed at
enormous expense, either within military industry or by state-subsidized R&D
in the civilian economy, without regard to cost. Subsidies to capital
accumulation, R&D, and technical education radically distort the forms taken
by production. … Blockbuster factories and economic centralization become
artificially profitable, thanks to the interstate highway system and other means
of externalizing distribution costs. |
|
Lastly, Nathan Goodman uses the
Hayekian knowledge problem to discuss the issue of privilege
in society. |
|
He quotes Hayek, saying: |
|
Today it is almost heresy to suggest that
scientific knowledge is not the sum of all knowledge. But a little reflection will
show that there is beyond question a body of very important but unorganized
knowledge which cannot possibly be called scientific in the sense of knowledge of
general rules: the knowledge of the particular circumstances of time and place. It
is with respect to this that practically every individual has some advantage over
all others because he possesses unique information of which beneficial use might
be made, but of which use can be made only if the decisions depending on it are
left to him or are made with his active cooperation. |
|
Nathan explains Hayek’s position by
way of example: |
|
The disability rights movement has for years
organized under the slogan “Nothing About Us Without Us” and opposed many
groups that try to make decisions related to disability without ever consulting
anyone who has a disability. For example, Autism Speaks, one of the largest autism
related non-profits, has never had an autistic person on its board. In spite of
their name, they do not speak for autistic people, but rather over us. They have
put out fear-mongering propaganda about autism that many autistic people, me
included, find highly offensive. They promote programs and “cures” that
autistic people find utterly unhelpful and counterproductive. They should examine
how autistic people may possess knowledge of autism that they lack. In other
words, they should acknowledge distributed knowledge and check their privilege. |
|
Keep in mind that saying “check
your privilege” doesn’t necessarily entail telling someone to shut up. It’s
akin to Ayn Rand’s “check your premises” in that it “…is an attempt to
get people to recognize the limits of their knowledge”. |
|